Performativi i refleksivna komunikacijska namera
Performatives and reflexive communicative intention
Author
Stojanović Prelević, Ivana LjMentor
Lazović, ŽivanCommittee members
Božičković, Vojislav
Jandrić, Andrej

Metadata
Show full item recordAbstract
U doktorskoj disertaciji ispitujemo da li je Ostinovo (John L. Austin) odbacivanje distinkcije
performativ/konstativ opravdano. Glavni razlog za odbacivanje ove distinkcije Ostin je video u
tome što se, s jedne strane, procena konstativa u terminima istinitosti/lažnosti može proširiti i na
performative, dok se, sa druge strane, procena performativa u terminima uspešnosti, prikladnosti
i sl., može primeniti i na konstative. Zbog toga se Ostin okreće analizi govornih činova uopšte,
koji se međusobno razlikuju po takozvanoj ilokucionoj snazi. Složićemo se sa Ostinovim relativizovanjem
distinkcije performativ/konstativ, ali ne i sa proširenjem primene kriterijuma istinitosti.
Kvalifikacija uspešno/neuspešno se može primeniti na konstative, posmatrane kao vrstu performativa,
dok se kvalifikacija istinito/lažno ne može primeniti na ostale vrste performativa. Dok se
kvalifikacija istinito/lažno odnosi na iskaze, distinkcija uspešno/neuspešno odnosi se na govorne
činove.
U prvom poglavlju odre...đujemo distinkciju performativ/konstativ odvojivši implicitne od
eksplicitnih performativa, i izlažemo Ostinove uslove za uspešne performative, kao i Ostinovu klasifikaciju
ilokucionih snaga. Ostin razlikuje pet vrsta ilokucionih snaga i to: verdiktive, egzercitive,
komisive, behabitive i ekspozitive. Ne slažemo se sa Ostinom da se verdiktivi i egzercitivi mogu
odnositi samo na sudije i službena lica, i dajemo primere u kojima se oni primenjuju i na druge
osobe. Verdiktive i egzercitive delimo na jake i slabe: prvi se tiču službenih a drugi neslužbenih
lica. Takođe uvodimo tri nova konteksta u kojima se egzercitivi javljaju (§ 1.5).
U drugom poglavlju ispitujemo ulogu namere u procesu komunikacije, vrste namera i refleksivnu
komunikacijsku nameru. Polazeći od pretpostavke da je za uspešan proces komunikacije
neophodno prepoznavanje značenja izricanja, ispitujemo neke od različitih stanovišta kako bismo
došli do odgovora na pitanje: Kako određujemo značenje izricanja? Tako u drugom poglavlju
(§ 2.1) objašnjavamo pojmove „Ono što je rečeno“ i „Ono što je implicirano“, u § 2.2 značenje
Grajsovog pojma refleksivne namere i u § 2.2.1. Serlov prigovor Grajsovom određenju refleksivne
komunikacijske namere. Serl smatra da se govornikovo značenje odnosi na nameru da se kod
slušaoca proizvede izvestan efekat, a kod slušaoca je razumevanje izricanja povezano sa prepoznavanjem
te namere. On prigovara Grajsu da ne dovodi u vezu prepoznavanje namere sa razumevanjem.
Ne slažemo se sa Serlovim prigovorom pozivajući se na shemu 1 (str. 43), koja pokazuje da
se značenje izricanja razume putem prepoznavanja namere i razumevanja govornikovog značenja.
Pojmu namere pristupamo iz ugla sledećih teorija: filozofske pragmatike (Grajs, Rekanati), teorije
relevancije (Sperber i Vilsonova) i lingvističke komunikacije (Kent Bah). Nalazimo da je Bahova
referencijalna namera slična Grajsovoj refleksivnoj nameri. Referencijalna namera deo je
komunikacijske namere...
This dissertation examines whether John Austin′s rejection of the performative/constative
distinction is justified. He rejects this distinction because, on the one hand, he believes that the
evaluation of constatives in terms of trutfullness can be extended to performatives, and that the
evaluation of performatives in terms of happy/unhappy distinction can be extended to constatives,
on the other. For these reasons, he turns to providing an analysis of illocutionary acts in general,
which can be distinguished by the so called “illocutionary force”. In the dissertation, Austin′s
relativization of the performative/constative distinction is accepted, while his extension of the
criterion of truthfullness to performatives is questioned. The happy/unhappy qualification can be
applied to constatives, when considered as performatives, but the true/false qualificaton cannot be
applied to other kinds of performatives. While the true/false qualification is related to propositions,
the happy/unhap...py distinction is related to speech acts.
In the first chapter, we define the performatives/constatives distinction distinguishes implicit
from explicit performatives, and put forward Austin′s conditions for happy performatives, as well
as Austin′s classification of illocutionary forces. Austin distinguishes between five classes of illocutionary
forces: verdictives, egzercitives, commissives, behabitives and expositives. We do not accept
Austin′s claim according to which verdictives and egzercitives rely only on judges and official
persons, and gives examples in which verdictives and egzercitives are applied to other persons.
We distinguishe between strong and weak readings of verdictives and egzercitives: the former are
meant for official persons, while the latter are meant for unofficial persons.
In the second chapter, the role of intention in the process of communication, as well as the
kinds of intention and reflexive communicative intention are analyzed. The analysis starts off with
a supposition that for a successful process of communication we have to recognize the meaning
of an utterance. The chapter proceeds by exploring some different views on how to determine the
meaning of an utterance. In this chapter, the key notions that are relevant for this work are laid out.
For example, “What is said” and “What is implicated” phrases are explained in the § 2.1. Grice′s
notion of reflexive communicative intention is spelled out in the § 2.2, while in the § 2.2.1. Searle′s
objection to Grice′s definition of reflexive communicative intention is presented. Searle claims that
the speaker′s meaning is related to an intention in order to produce effects to a hearer, while the
hearer’s understanding of an utterance is related to the recognition of speaker’s intention. Searle
objects to Grice that he doesn’t tie the recognition of meaning of an utterance with the recognition
of intention. We challenge Searle’s objection by using schema 1 (p. 43). which shows that the
recognition of utterance relies on the recognition of speaker′s meaning and intention. The notion
of intention is analyzed in relation to the following theories: philosophical pragmatics (Grice, Recanati),
psychological pragmatics (Sperber & Wilson) and linguistic communication (Kent Bach).
We find out that Bach′s notion of referential intention is similiar to Grice′s notion of reflexive communicative
intention. The referential intention is a part of the communicative intention, by which
we are enabled to pick out the object of reference...